List

Aristotle – On Rhetoric

*******These  are just a collection of reflections on this work, NOT an outline or organized, sustained treatment.  🙂

According to Kennedy, “The great strength of On Rhetoric derives from its clear recognition (in contrast to views expressed by Plato) that rhetoric is a technique or tool applicable to any subject and from the universality and utility of its basic, systematically organized, concepts. (20).  These include frameworks for:

1. The identification of three (and only three) pisteis, or forms of persuasion, derived from the factors in any speech situation:

  • a. Presentation of the trustworthy character of the speaker (the speaker in the rhetorical triangle)
  • b. The logical argument set out in the text (the text in the rhetorical triangle)
  • c. The emotional effect created by the speaker and text on the audience or reader (the audience in the rhetorical triangle)

2. The distinction of three (and only three) species of rhetoric, based on whether the audience is or is not a judge, in the sense of being able to take specific action as a result of being persuaded to do so, and the time with which each species is concerned (this theory of rhetoric situates its practice in the civic discourse):

  • a. If a judge of past actions, the species is judicial (entheymeme is best)
  • b. If a judge of future action, the species is deliberative (paradigm is best)
  • c. If an observer of the speech, not called on to take action, the species is epideictic (amplification is best)

3.  Each of these species has its characteristic “end,” the principal issue with which it is concerned:

  • a. The end of judicial rhetoric is justice
  • b. The end of deliberative rhetoric is the best interest of the audience
  • c. The end of epideictic rhetoric is praise or blame of the subject

4.  3 Forms of persuasion are either:

  • a. Non-artistic: direct evidence (facts, witnesses, documents, etc.) that the speaker uses but does not—or should not— invent; or
  • b. Artistic: logical arguments constructed by the speaker, of two types:

i. Inductive argument, called paradigm, or example,
drawing a particular conclusion from one or more
parallels
ii. Deductive argument, called enthymeme, or rhetorical
syllogism, drawing a conclusion from stated or
implied premises

5 . In rhetoric the speaker or writer almost always deals with probabilities—what could have happened or can happen based on what happens for the most part in such situations.

6 . The materials of enthymemes come from the premises of other disciplines, especially politics and ethics, but their formal structure draws on topics, strategies of argument useful in dealing with any subject. (21)

Thoughts/Questions:

I think there are some interesting resonances between Aristotle’s consideration of dialectic & rhetoric and what is happening in some works we’re reading in other classes right now – namely Byron Hawk’s Counter-History of Composition: Toward Methodologies of Complexity.  Whereas Kennedy sees rhetoric as a relatively one-sided affair (the speaker operates canonically to produce a speech), dialectic operates in a two-sided fashion (by definition, right?); however, rhetoric conceived on Hawk’s terms is multiplicitous and always in the act of becoming/creation.  I wonder how much static-ness is attributed to Aristotle’s work because of its operation as a handbook as opposed to a loose set of proscriptions for how to deal with changing rhetorical situations (or ecologies).  I wonder if the one-sidedness we see in Kennedy’s description of the “handbook Aristotle” is all that accurate.

Despite the influence of Plato it would appear that Aristotle too conceives of argument in terms of probability.  He notes this in Book I, Section 11 (34) and again when discussing the enthymeme Book I, Section 14 (42), and again in Book I, Chapter 12 (92-100), and again in the section on “Past and Future Fact” (160-1).

I am really interested in how we see the topoi (172-184) operating in Aristotle’s discussion of the rhetorical commonplaces.  He provides us with a pretty detailed theory of what particular “commonplaces” yield particular argumentative strategies.  My question is one of the relationship between topoi and rhetorical invention.  Do we consider the commonplaces as either 1)  designed to help writers to create new knowledge (epistemic) and reach new insights and judgments? Or 2) is its purpose to help writers to find and deploy existing information and lines of argument to supports theses or judgments already known?  Because they are somewhat proscriptive, the topoi seem to lead rhetors to the discovery of existing knowledge for argumentative purposes.  To phrase it differently, Carolyn Miller provides this definition of the topoi: “a hunter may know what they track or may unexpectedly discover new game; however, they do not invent their quarry” – in other words, the topoi may serve as a dwelling place for the hunt; however, the hunter doesn’t simply call into being (invent) the game.  So, according to this perspective, the topoi – and rhetorical invention on a larger scale – offer the student a way to discover lines of argument/theses to support their arguments; however, they aren’t involved in the creation of new knowledge from the topoi.  But this too seems unlikely when we consider the specificity of situations wherein the topoi are utilized . . . in other words, all situations might call for a particular line of argument/commonplace as framing; however, the specificity of the situation – the “each particular case” – seems to call for the creation of new knowledge relative to the situation (but still nested inside a broader categorization of commonplace that already exists).  Again, relying on Hawk, the answer might lie in Aristotle’s conception of entelechy.  Hawk claims that Aristotle’s notion of “entelechy” is the immanent goal that lies in the process of achieving it.  If we think about invention as generative and always developing more (an invention of “and”) then it might be easy to think of the topoi as commonplaces that direct the discovery of new knowledge that is contextual (audience and situation dependent) and always changing. . . . all that sounds awesome; however, how in the world would we ever teach that to students?!?

Aristotle notes that different kinds of speech are particularly suited to the aims: 1) amplification is useful for the epideictic; 2) paradigms (predictions based on past examples) are best for deliberative; 3) enthymemes are best for judicial (because of their logical qualities in determining the cause and demonstration of an event that happened in the past) (82-3).

Aristotle anticipates – at least to some degree – the Ciceronian “good man speaking well” by noting that some speakers are persuasive because they have practical wisdom (phronesis), virtue (arete), and good will (eunoia) (112).  There are further convergences between the two in their unified objection to anger because of its ability to diminish the ethos of the speaker (121-3).  Does the section on “fear” give a fairly Machiavellian take on human nature (human beings are naturally inclined toward evil/wrong)?

Notes From Class:

1.  The enthymeme as unifying structure in Rhetoric – strung throughout.  Grimaldi’s position.

2.  Dialectic (based on syllogism – general premise + minor premise = conclusion) all premises are stated and the general premise is operating on an absolute truth of sorts, rhetoric (based on enthymeme – major premise isn’t necessarily stated,based on probable premises [not absolutes] ).

3.  Aristotle’s “to see the available means of persuasion” is a two-fold sort of statement – not to engage in eristic argument, but to speak from a position of the good toward a sort of truth and against the sophistic definition of argumentation as only success – process not product (Kennedy 36).

4.  Rhetoric’s utilization of examples (arguments from induction – working from an individual observation of the world) isn’t as preferable to rhetoric as the enthymatic reasoning (working on a shared knowledge of the world).  This model is inverted by the empiricists in the 17th/18th century by people like Bacon, Hume, etc..  This is a binary about epitemic creation wherein knowledge is either objective/individualist or subjective/collective.

5. Psychological approach to rhetoric by considering the ways that emotions operate in rhetorical situations (Book II).

6.  Fallacies aren’t logically problematic but are often more so problematic based on audience/context/probability (Kennedy 185-9).

Leave a Reply

  Tag: judicial rhetoric